Distinctions between art and craft have been treated as an important issue in the art world since the Renaissance. Indeed, the entire discipline of art history is based upon a qualitative analysis which would elevate particular classes of objects and make light of others. However, they appear a fiction when we examine art history before the Renaissance. Why have certain art objects been selected to be part of art history while others were not? Were they selected to represent an aesthetic significance or were they a mere matter of convenience? The purpose of this paper is to examine the historical process in which an art object has been placed in either a craft category or a fine art category and explore how the dividing line between art and craft has been bolstered by social, ideological, and institutional system. Greek and Latin writers did not distinguish between fine arts and craft, using the word ‘art’ to refer to a skilled craft or science rather than to a creative activity. However, two complementary groups of arts were distinguished: the liberal versus the mechanical. The intellectual labor of the liberal arts was placed above the physical labor of the mechanical. The liberal arts encompassed intellectual activities and skills, such as grammar, rhetoric, astronomy, as well as music and poetry. The mechanical arts, on the other hand, included manual activities, ranging from weaving, wood carving, agriculture, pottery, and navigation to armament, in which subgroup were also found painting, sculpture, and architecture. During the medieval period, ongoing contempt for manual labor was mitigated by the moral value of work and self-sufficiency within the monastic way of life. Italian Renaissance artists and humanists claimed tor the visual arts the same intellectual status as that of poetry and music, and leaving behind among the mechanical arts what would become known as craft. Renaissance theorists reinforced the intellectual and artistic claims of the visual arts by establishing academies devoted exclusively to painting, sculpture, and architecture, the three “arti del disegno.” With the help of these academies, the visual arts acquired an identity distinct from that of the mechanical arts, one that paved the way for the later notion of the fine arts. Although Renaissance theorists furthered the conceptual claims of visual arts, they did not link these claims to a concept of beauty in art. A theory of fine arts emerged clearly only in the eighteenth century, when such thinkers as Burke, Baumgarten, and Kant developed new philosophical principles for judging artistic beauty. Kant himself reinforced the notion of the division of mental and manual labor by presenting it as a transcendental necessity. This transformation introduced a theoretical border between the fine arts and all other arts. Although this distinction may have helped to clarify the nature of those activities now considered the fine arts, it left behind an ill-assorted group of activities under the medieval term mechanical arts. This type of discourse is also found in R.G. Collingwood’s Principles of Art in which he argues, it is necessary to disentangle the notion of craft from that of art proper in order to take the first step towards a sound aesthetic. Thus it is quite possible to say that the history of craft has been shaped by its exclusion from art history. The exclusion of craft is socially created and constantly reaffirmed by the gatekeepers of classical art history and aesthetics. The legacy of the hierarchical preoccupation with ‘lower’ and ‘higher’ forms of art has become so embedded in Western thought that it persists even today. Thus the deconstruction of the distinction between art and craft helps in dismantling the hegemonic framework for the triumph of modernism. In fact post-modernists and feminist art historians are deconstructing many of the most cherished assumptions of art history and aesthetics, especially the hierarchical system of arts, in order to achieve a more balanced view.